Book Review: Calvin and the
Whigs: A Study in Historical Political
Philosophy
“Like all other knowledge, our knowledge of
God consists of certain propositions or truths. No doubt it is true that “that
which God reveals of himself...is so rich and deep [presumably Bavinck means
extensive and complicated] that it can never be fully known by any human
individual.” But this is not because the knowledge of God is a peculiar and
different type of knowledge: It is because life is too short to gain an understanding
of the Bible. The defect lies in the shortness of human life, and often in the
mediocrity of the man, not in the understandability of the revelation, for all
Scripture is profitable for doctrine.”
Gordon H. Clark.
The Trinity (Kindle Locations
1529-1533). The Trinity Foundation.
Ruben Alvarado. Calvinism
and the Whigs: A Study in Historical
Political Philosophy. (Aalten: Pantocrator Press, 2017).
The author of this work of
historiography kindly sent me a review copy of the book. But in keeping with my commitment to offer
solid critical reviews as I have done before, I will simply say what I truly
think. His book purports to explicate
the Huguenot point of view of political philosophy and to survey the evolution
of political constitutionalism from the divine right of kings to a
constitutionalism based on the Presbyterian or Calvinist view of political
philosophy as advocated by the French Huguenots and their influence on the Dutch
Reformed form of government as it existed under the Calvinist view of
constitutionalism. It is the thesis of
the book that modern concepts of natural law are a departure from a more
Christian worldview and political constitutionalism which, under the social
contract theory of Hugo Grotius and John Locke, deteriorated into the
secularist and anti-Christian civil religion of modernity.
As I am no expert in historiography I will
only speak to what I can legitimately discern and deduce from the book based on
the Calvinism of the late Dr. Gordon H. Clark as I can best understand his
views. At the outset I should
acknowledge that I think Dr. Clark would have agreed that John Locke’s
political philosophy and social contract theory ultimately leads to totalitarianism. On that I can wholeheartedly agree with the
author.
However, I should also point out
that in my short life and due to the work load I have, I cannot claim to have
time or resources to give a more detailed critique and review of Mr. Alvarado’s
book. While the quote from Dr. Clark
above pertains to Bavinck’s doctrine of the unknowability of God, I think it
also applies to how much learning is possible in this life. It is not that I cannot learn more political
philosophy and historiography but that in my short life of 57 years that has
not been the primary focus of my personal studies after college and seminary.
I was troubled a bit by his
giving credit in the foreward to the book to both Peter Leithart and Gary North
for reviewing the manuscript. I was
troubled because Leithart is a promoter of the heresy of the Federal Vision and
Gary North is an advocate of the theonomy movement. From a Clarkian Scripturalist persepective
this could indicate some presupposed biases on the part of the author. However, in a Facebook message to me, Mr.
Alvarado assured me that the reviews by Leithart and North were done several
years ago prior to Leithart’s departure into the Federal Vision realm. Also troubling was the use of the term
“theocracy” to refer to the Calvinist form of government in Geneva and
Holland. I am not sure how Alvarado is
defining theocracy. Perhaps he means
theonomic? Technically speaking there
are no prophets or apostles today nor were there any prophets in Geneva or
Holland. In order for there to be a true
theocracy it would be required for there to be ongoing revelation from God as
the case was with Moses, Joshua, and to a lesser extent, with the nation of
Israel under the rule of David and Solomon, etc. Since the Bible is the only special
revelation from God today, political philosophy must be logically deduced
from the Scriptures by good and necessary consequence. (Westminster
Confession of Faith 1:6).
The book is very detailed. The problem with this is that I got bogged
down in the inductive aspects of the book and the analysis. But careful reading does yield several good
points made by the author. However, I
was somewhat troubled by the fact that though the book is supposed to compare
and contrast the Calvinist view of political constitutionalism and Whig
political philosophy and constitutionalism, the author never fully defines
either term. On the one hand, he seems
to say that the Calvinism of Geneva, Holland, and England under the Glorious
Revolution are all Calvinist, he then proceeds to say that some Calvinists and
Puritans under the Glorious Revolution were latitudinarians. And on the other hand, even in the beginning
of the book, Alvarado never defines exactly what a Whig is. He simply presupposes that we all already
know what a Whig is, although we are told that John Locke is a representative
of the Whig political constitutionalism in England. Also, to avoid any confusion, it should be
pointed out that the Glorious
Revolution is not the same event as the English Civil War or
the Cromwellian Revolution. (See
also: English
Whig Party).
As best I can understand,
however, it seems that the Whigs were a British political party who opposed the
Tories. The Whigs advocated for a
constitutional government that compromised between the authority of a monarch
and a more representative government of elected officials in the Parliament as
opposed to the Tory advocacy for the divine right of absolute authority for the
monarchy:
This
historiographical predilection presents Whigs as those who stood for progress,
liberty, and parliamentary government; Tories, as those who stood for reaction,
repression, and absolutist monarchy. . .
. The Whigs gained the predominance in England in 1688, in the wake of the
so-called Glorious Revolution, in which William III of Orange assumed the
throne, upon abdication of James II.
They proceeded to transform English society. Their innovations proved so popular that
England became the model of enlightened progress in Europe. By the early nineteenth century everyone
within the orbit of English politics and society had become permeated with
their particular orientation, so much so that all the new political movements
operated on terms the Whigs had established, thus in terms of post-Whig
agendas, with this fundamental set of beliefs as common ground. (Alvarado, pp. 1-2).
The basic thesis of the book is
not about Calvin himself but about the theological and philosophical legacy of
Calvin as it became known later as Calvinism.
In that view I would say that the book would have been better titled as
Calvinism and the Whigs since Calvin himself predates the English Civil War,
the Glorious Revolution, and Hugo Grotius and John Locke. The author goes through a somewhat lengthy
argument tracing the roots of constitutionalism and social contract theory all
the way back to Augustine’s two kingdoms or two cities view of political and
ecclesiastical authority or the two swords view of society. According to the author, both Calvinism and
Roman Catholicism have in common the two swords view and he then links together
the Augustinians in both the papist camp and the Calvinist camp and says that
both the papists and the Calvinists were favorable to a theocratic or theonomic
view of the political constitutional system of government.
While I find his discussion of
the development of Hugo Grotius’s natural law theory and the connection to John
Locke’s social contract theory interesting and a fairly good analysis, it is
troubling that the author thinks the problem originated with Grotius’s Arminianism
and Locke’s latitudinarianism. He
overlooks the fact that Calvinism is deduced from the Bible. The author in fact hardly ever mentions the
Bible in his historiographical analysis or his analysis of political philosophy. The main difference between Roman Catholicism
and Calvinism is not latitudinarianism but the source of authority. Calvinism derives its philosophy of political
contract from the Bible, not from the church.
Roman Catholicism places the authority of the church above the authority
of Scripture and emphasizes natural law every bit as much as Hugo Grotius and
John Locke did. This seems to be a
typical error of theonomists in general where they think Roman Catholicism is a
good thing and not part of the very latitudinarianism they complain about. Furthermore, the author fails to see that
placing the sacraments into the political realm and requiring political office
holders to partake of the sacraments as keys to the kingdom opens the door for
the very abuses that led to the halfway covenant in the Puritan colonies during
the time of Jonathan Edwards and his grandfather:
This points,
finally, to a subject which is universally neglected by modern historians
because its importance is simply not recognized. Perhaps the key issue of concrete debate
during and after the Reformation concerned the nature of the sacrament of the Lord’s
Supper. . . . But the judicial element
involved is neglected: that the
administration of the sacraments served to apply judicial decrees concerning
inclusion in or exclusion from the Kingdom of Christ. The ministers in applying these keys were
acting in the place of Christ passing judgments in terms of His decrees. Thus, the administration of the sacraments
was considered “binding and loosing:” the application of the very judicial
decree of Christ in a particular situation.
Precisely this power, the ramifications of which extend throughout a
social order based in Christian faith, was what the secular and lay powers were
concerned to remove. And that explains
the fierceness with which this debate was conducted.
Alvarado, pp.
172-173.
Worse, Alvarado has what can only
be called a papist view of the sacraments here because the sacraments from a Calvinist perspective are held
to be keys to the kingdom only in regards to church membership. There is no necessary connection between
election, regeneration, and church membership.
In fact, the invisible church is composed only of the elect while the
visible church is fallible and has members who are both elect and reprobate. The ministers of the Gospel and the Gospel
sacraments are not vicars of Christ acting in the place of Christ. The fact is the Westminster Confession of
Faith outright denies that ministers are vicars of Christ. Christ alone is the head of the church:
To these
officers the keys of the kingdom of heaven are committed, by virtue whereof,
they have power, respectively, to retain, and remit sins; to shut that kingdom
against the impenitent, both by the Word, and censures; and to open it unto
penitent sinners, by the ministry of the Gospel; and by absolution from
censures, as occasion shall require. (WCF 30:2 WCS)
The Calvinist and Protestant view
is that the Gospel and right belief in doctrinal matters is just as important
as sanctification issues and the ministers are not the emphasis. Rather, the Bible is the final authority,
which is why Scripture is given the highest priority in the doctrinal and
propositional system of theology deduced from the Bible by good and necessary
consequence:
The whole
counsel of God, concerning all things necessary for His own glory, man's
salvation, faith and life, is either expressly set down in Scripture, or by
good and necessary consequence may be deduced from Scripture: unto which
nothing at any time is to be added, whether by new revelations of the Spirit,
or traditions of men. Nevertheless, we acknowledge the inward illumination of
the Spirit of God to be necessary for the saving understanding of such things
as are revealed in the word; and that there are some circumstances concerning
the worship of God, and government of the Church, common to human actions and
societies, which are to be ordered by the light of nature, and Christian
prudence, according to the general rules
of the word, which are always to be observed. (WCF 1:6 WCS)
That being said, I found many of
the points made during the discussion convincing. I am not a theonomist or a supporter of
theocracy. However, it is worthwhile to
consider that political philosophy should be deduced from the Bible since all
knowledge begins with Scripture. The
author argues that when the role of the family in society is changed to
individualism the result is a latitudinarianism whereby individual rights trump
what is best for society as a whole. On
that point I can wholeheartedly agree but it should not be forgotten that God
ordained the family in creation. Natural
law is nothing more than a form of utilitarian ethics whereby a plurality of
individuals who emphasize individual freedom gain control and overpower the
biblical values and principles upon which the society was originally
founded. It is literally true that
whatever each person thinks is right becomes right. But this overlooks the total depravity of the
fallen human race and the noetic effects of sin
(Psalm 14:1-3; Romans 3:10-23; Romans 8:7). This is another reason I object to the author’s
downplaying of Roman Catholic complicity in latitudinarianism in the political
realm, especially since Vatican II.
Basically the Roman Catholic Church is advocating full blown Pelagianism and not even
semi-Pelagian anymore.
I object to the neo-orthodox
views of the Van Tilian political philosophy whereby the church is to withdraw
from the civic realm and allow the ungodly to rule the civic realm and the
church should rule the ecclesiastical realm.
Ironically, theonomy originated with Cornelius Van Til’s theology and
was promoted by Greg Bahnsen and others.
The author of this book is part of that theonomic philosophy and
theology as far as I can tell. Yet Van
Til’s views also led to the very latitudinarianism to which theonomists
object! This is why you have the
Westminster Seminary, California theology that emphasizes a total disconnect
between the church and the political realm and another stream that originates
from the Westminster Seminary, Philadelphia theology. It is my opinion that both the disjunction
between church and state that leads to the anti-Christian values of secular
humanism and latitudinarianism and the theonomic view that emphasizes
ecclesiastical militancy above biblical authority both lead to the same
place. That is unless our political
philosophy is deduced from the Bible the end result will always be skepticism
and totalitarianism.
Furthermore, I find it ironic
that certain advocates of Clarkian Scripturalism have basically endorsed a form
of secular humanism in reaction to their objections to Van Til’s theology and
the theonomic views deduced from Van Til.
John Robbins, for example, worked for Ron Paul and supported Ron Paul’s
political philosophy of libertarianism.
Every man literally does what is right in his own eyes. Let it be said that Gordon H. Clark never
agreed with libertarianism because it can never be deduced from the Bible. On the other hand, theonomy is problematic
because it leads to theological errors like the Federal Vision,
semi-pelagianism, Arminianism and neo-orthodoxy. The Westminster Seminary, California theology
is equally problematic because it leads to antinomianism and latitudinarianism
even more quickly. Lee Irons and hiswife, Misty, for example, are spearheading LGBTQ rights in the civic realm due
to the view that the two kingdoms are totally disjunctive and the one has
nothing to do with the other. Basically
neo-orthodoxy leads to two extremes of what can only be called civil
religion. The theonomic civil religion
endorses the latitudinarianism of theological pluralism and has no problem with
the idolatries of Rome so long as biblical morality is loosely adhered to. The antinomianism of the neo-orthodox views
of Westminster California leads to endorsing perversion as a “natural” right in
the civic realm and is therefore a form of atheism and secular humanism. While the author does oppose the Westminster
California endorsement of natural law, he seems to think that Roman Catholicism
and Calvinism have something in common, which they do not.
I do recommend this book because
the author does a good job of tracing the history of natural law and his
explanation of what is wrong with natural law is worthy of consideration. His view of the Dutch Calvinist government is
also interesting. However, he never
mentions the fact that the cause of the fall of the Dutch Calvinist government
can also be tied directly to the three points of common grace espoused by
Abraham Kuyper, who also advocated for a peace treaty and co-belligerency
between Calvinism and Rome. The author
seems to think that certain Calvinists rejected Calvin’s two sword view of the
church and state and advocated latitudinarianism after the Glorious
Revolution. But the real problem is that
the doctrine of common grace is semi-Arminian and raises natural revelation and
natural law to the same level as biblical or special revelation and in fact
undermines the Bible as the axiom for a solid epistemology for a Christian
worldview and for a political theology and philosophy. When common grace is emphasized above and
beyond the special revelation of Scripture the result is skepticism because
science and the arts gain equal authority to Scripture and it is not long
before the very latitudinarianism that the author opposes results. The Westminster divines were careful to
exclude the traditions of men as a source of authority and it is troubling that
Alvarado sees the Roman Catholic Church in such a positive light. It in fact raises the question of whether or
not Alvarado is in fact pushing a version of the Federal Vision heresy where
culture and sacraments trump biblical Christianity? Does he also disagree with the biblical
definition of justification as do the Federal Visionists?
As I said before, the analysis of
the historical development of secular humanism and social contract theory in
the book is helpful. But I cannot agree with
the author that his brand of theocracy or theonomy is a solution to the
problem. As Dr. Gordon H. Clark so aptly
pointed out:
By what right
does a government exist? Those who
reject divine revelation base the state either on naked power and brutality, or
on some sort of social contract, or on a natural development from the
family. Elsewhere I have argued in
detail that the latter two reduce to the first;
with the result that secularism eventuates in dictatorship and totalitarian
rule. It is only in the Hebrew-Christian
revelation, e.g. in the account of King Ahab and Naboth’s vineyard, that the
rightful power of government is limited.
Dr. Gordon H.
Clark. “The Civil Magistrate,” in Essays
on Ethics and Politics. John
Robbins, ed. (Jefferson: Trinity Foundation, 1992). Pp.
22-23.
No comments:
Post a Comment
No anonymous comments. Your comments may or may not be posted if you insist on not standing by your words with your real identification.