"Today . . . many people hold that crime is
only a disease; the criminal is not
guilty, but sick; and even his sickness
is the result of a misguided society rather than of a depraved individual mind
or will."
"Naturally: Socialism is
anti-Christian."
Dr. Gordon H. Clark.
Gordon H. Clark on the Atonement and Socialism: Quote of the Day
It can be confusing to think
logically at first. That is because
thinking logically requires some study of logic and the fallacious arguments
used by opponents of Christianity. The
basic axiom for the Christian worldview is that the Bible is the starting point
for all knowledge. In light of that, Dr.
Gordon H. Clark makes the following observations concerning the justice of God
in regards to the atonement by quoting Jonathan Edwards and a couple of Edwards’
invalid arguments in regards to the moral government and the application of the
moral law by moral agents. Clark is an astute critic of invalid arguments
since he was an expert in logic. (John
1:9).
[ . . . that he might be just,
and the justifier of him which believeth in Jesus. (Rom. 3:26 KJV)]
Romans
3:26: . . . that he might be just and
the justifier of the one who has faith in Jesus. [NKJV?]
This verse says
something about the justice of God,
and the justice of God is a most important facet of the doctrine of the
Atonement. But at the moment we are
interested only in the method used to
defend divine justice. Here is an
example.
Jonathan Edwards
wrote a thirty-five page article Concerning
the Necessity and Reasonableness of the Christian Doctrine of Satisfaction for
Sin (Works, Volume VIII, 1811). He
introduces his subject with the proposition, “Justice requires that sin be
punished.” He appeals to the universal
belief that “some crimes are so horrid . . . that it is requisite they should
not go unpunished unless . . . some measure [of compensation or repentance] at
least balances the desert of punishment.”
In Edwards’ day hardly anyone would have disagreed, and thus Edwards
could rely on the commonly held view as a sufficient introduction to his
theology. Today that is not the
case. Many people hold that crime is
only a disease; the criminal is not
guilty, but sick; and even his sickness
is the result of a misguided society rather than of a depraved individual mind
or will. If then it be our business to
maintain the truth of the Christian doctrine of Atonement, instead of merely
explaining it, we must face a problem Edwards hardly dreamed of. In view of the prevalent behaviorism and
Freudian psychology, we cannot rely on common opinion and so-called human
reason. Yet if we rely on revelation
alone, are we not begging the question and losing our audience? Edwards could plausibly appeal to human
reason because the human reason he was acquainted with was English reason
already permeated with Christian ideas.
But this is no longer the case.
Edwards thought that crime excites “such an abhorrence and indignation
that . . . by this all is granted that needs to be granted, to show that desert
of punishment carries in it a requisiteness of the punishment deserved”
(500). But today the behaviorists (for
example John Watson and B. F. Skinner) aim to remove the idea of punishment
from the laws and from the mind of man.
Sweden, for example, has made it illegal for parents to spank their
children or even to scold them.
Naturally: Socialism is
anti-Christian.
From the
eighteenth-century Christian opinion that all crime demands punishment, unless
there be something to balance it, Edwards infers that, since any sin against
God is so great that nothing can balance it, God must punish it. “If any ask, why God could not pardon the
injury on repentance, without other satisfaction, without wrong to justice; I
ask the same person why he could not also pardon the injury without repentance?” To Edwards this is unthinkable, but few today
would acknowledge that his argument is valid.
On the next page (502) he appeals not only to a Christian conscience,
but also to the “consciences of heathen.”
Yet he must add the damaging proviso “unless conscience has been stupefied
by frequent violations.” On page 506 he
also admits “all but Epicureans will own that all moral agents are subjects of
God’s moral government.” This is a false
statement. Others than Epicureans are
also such exceptions. Of course Jonathan
Edwards antedated the modern Logical Positivists (who are far from being
Epicureans) but in addition to Democritus, not even Aristotle satisfies Edwards’
assertion. For that matter, even one
exception to his norm destroys his position.
Yet from his inadequate observation he concludes that therefore God’s
conscience must be like ours. Hence
Edwards’ argument fails on two counts.:
invalid inference and false premises.
Dr. Gordon H.
Clark. The Atonement. Lois A.
Zeller and Elizabeth Clark George.
1987. (Trinity Foundation: Hobbs, 1996).
Second edition. Pp. 5-7.
[See also: The Atonement.]
No comments:
Post a Comment
No anonymous comments. Your comments may or may not be posted if you insist on not standing by your words with your real identification.