Hyper-Calvinism, Common Grace, Libertarianism and the Simplicity of God
(Part 2)
[See: Part
1]
Common Grace
The reader will have to forgive
me if I take an ad hoc approach to my blog posts as my time is limited and I do
work a full time job. My posts are
sometimes sporadic for that reason.
However, at this point I would like to consider the three points of common
grace and why I think Herman Hoeksema, David Engelsma and other fine
Protestant Reformed theologians have correctly assessed the problem with common
grace and why it leads to skepticism and even liberalism. For one thing, the doctrine of common grace
presupposes that all men are basically good except that they are partially
depraved due to Adam’s original sin. Obviously, this undermines the view that
humankind or mankind has been totally depraved or totally corrupted by the
curse of sin since the rebellion of Adam as the federal head of the human
race. (Romans 5:12-21). Whenever mankind has tried to use his
knowledge it is usually to build idolatrous edifices to reach heaven and to
assert his own sovereignty over creation apart from submission to Almighty
God. The biblical example is the tower
of Babel but in modern times technology, empirical science, secular philosophy,
and political science have all been used to usurp God’s sovereignty and to deny
God’s very existence. (Genesis 11:1-9
KJV; 1 Timothy 6:20 KJV; 2 Timothy 3:7 KJV).
For one thing, common grace
undermines the doctrine of total depravity.
Total depravity does not refer to the degree of an individual’s
wickedness but to the extent of the corruption of sin in the human nature. The human nature or being includes the human
body and the soul. Within the soul there
are the further distinctions between the volition or will and the intellect and
the emotions. However, the late Dr.
Gordon H. Clark would say that the emotions are strictly a result of bodily
sensations and would not include the emotions as part of the human soul. Although I somewhat agree that the body
produces emotional reactions and sensations, I do recognize that there is
interaction between the soul or heart of man and the physical body and these
emotional responses do affect the mind or soul.
Moreover, Clark further contended that since God is a spirit (John 4:24)
it logically follows that man is a soul living in a body and that the soul is
the image of God, not the human body.
Some have falsely accused Clark of Gnosticism on this account but that
does not follow since it is the Bible which says that the soul lives on in a
disembodied state after death until the resurrection for the final judgment of
both the elect and the reprobate. (2
Corinthians 5:6-8 KJV). God does judge
what we do in the body and the body is not the source of our sinful
corruptions, rather the original sin of Adam brought the curse of total
depravity or total inability on man’s soul and the curse of sin is passed on
from the souls of Adam and Eve to all their posterity by way of natural
generation. Dr. Clark rejected the view
that each soul is created with a sinful corruption by God but rather accepted
the traducian view espoused by W. G. T. Shedd in his systematic theology.
. . . the
theological argument strongly favors traducianism. The imputation of the first
sin of Adam to all his posterity as a culpable act is best explained and defended
upon the traducian basis. The Augustinian and Calvinistic anthropologies affirm
that the act by which sin came into the world of mankind was a self-determined
and guilty act and that it is justly chargeable upon every individual man
equally and alike. But this requires that the posterity of Adam and Eve should,
in some way or other, participate in it. Participation is the ground of merited
imputation, though not of unmerited or gratuitous imputation (Shedd on Rom.
4:3, 8). The posterity could not participate in the first sin in the form of
individuals, and hence they must have participated in it in the form of a race.
This supposes that the race-form is prior to the individual form, that man
first exists as a race or species and in this mode of existence commits a
single and common sin. The individual, now a separate and distinct unit, was
once a part of a greater whole. Westminster Shorter Catechism Q. 16 asserts the
commission of a common sin in the following terms: “All mankind, descending
from Adam by ordinary generation, sinned in him and fell with him in his first
transgression.” The term mankind denotes here the human nature before it was
individualized by propagation. This nature sinned. Human nature existing
primarily as a unity in Adam and Eve and this same human nature as subsequently
distributed and metamorphosed into the millions of individual men are two modes
of the same thing.
Shedd, William
G. Dogmatic Theology (Kindle
Locations 13910-13921). P&R Publishing. Kindle Edition.
It was also Clark’s contention
that even the good that men do is sinful because unbelieving men do nothing
they do in order to bring glory to God but to glorify themselves or some other
idol. (Proverbs 21:4). Even the plowing of the wicked is sin. This would mean that even the scientific
advancements made during the Renaissance and the Protestant Reformation period
over against medieval scholasticism was only beneficial insofar as it protected
God’s providential plans for the elect within the church and society. For those who were reprobate God’s providence
worked in the opposite direction. A good
example of that is given by Dr. Theodore Letis where he notes that Isaac Newton
upon discovering the issues with lower textual criticism rejected
trinitarianism and became a Socinian. [Due
to time constraints I neglected to note where the comment occurs but I am
almost certain that Letis’s remark is in this video: The Quest for the Historical
Text, the ESV, and the Jesus Seminar.]
Another modern example would be
Friedriech Nietzsche, the German philosopher of nihilism. Nietzshe’s father was a Lutheran
minister. After a severe illness
Nietzsche’s father died and the tragedy left Nietzsche questioning his faith. Later when he decided to accept a call to
ministry Nietzsche attended a Lutheran seminary where lower textual criticism
was being taught. The ultimate result
was that the assumption of corruptions in the text and that the corruptions
were made by those who wished to support orthodoxy led Nietzsche to reject his
Christian faith and become an atheist.
From that point on Nietzsche attacked Christianity and Christian
morality and ethics mercilessly until he actually went insane. He could never find a consistent worldview
and moral system to replace the apodictic ethical system of the moral law of
God in the Holy Scriptures. He was also
the inspiration for Hitler’s eugenics and the extermination of the Jewish
“vermin”. After all, might makes right,
according to Nietzsche. [See: Genius of the Modern
World: Friedriech Nietzsche.]
To make it more clear, I do not
believe that modern scholarship should be accepted by Evangelicals
uncritically. It could be legitimately
argued, as the Protestant Reformed brethren do, that common grace opened the
door to liberal lower and higher criticism.
I have not read all of Theodore Letis’s book, The Ecclesiastical Text, but he makes a compelling argument that B.
B. Warfield helped undermine Old Princeton by accepting the liberal axioms of
Westcott and Hort’s science of textual criticism. I would contend that this could be partly due
to the Stone Lectures delivered by Abraham Kuyper at Princeton seminary in 1898. [You can download a free ebook version in
epub or mobi from monergism.com: Stone Lectures.] Although Kuyper himself was a
presuppositionalist, his lectures lead evidentialists and the common sense
philosophers of Princeton to adopt a rationalist and empiricist approach to
defending the infallibility and inerrancy of Scripture. The downside is that Warfield, as noted by
Dr. Letis’s book, decided that corruptions had crept into the Bible and
corrections needed to be made. Warfield
advocated removing huge portions of Scripture as not in the autographs, including
the angel stirring the waters in the pool of Bethesda (John 5:3-4), the woman
caught in adultery (John 7:53-8:11), and the resurrection account of Mark’s
gospel narrative (Mark 16:9-20). Warfield reasoned that science alone could
prove what was originally in the autographs and it is my opinion that his
common sense philosophy, evidentialists apologetics, and his commitment to
empiricism as a basis for knowledge predisposed Warfield to question the
Scriptures. Although Warfield set out to
answer the more liberal text critics he failed to see that his wholesale
adoption of liberal axioms in doing textual critical work would lead to the
same skepticism of the radical liberal scholars. Basically, the Westminster Confession of
Faith presupposes that the copies made from the autographs are as fully
inspired as the autographs themselves despite their being apographa which
mediates the originals. (See WCF chapter
1).
I am aware of a letter that Letis
wrote to Dr. Clark in 1984 that is included in Doug Douma’s anthology of
Clark’s letters. But Clark died in 1985
and may not have answered Letis’s letter.
In that letter Letis acknowledges reading Dr. Clark’s article, “Logical Criticisms of
Textual Criticism,” Trinity Review,
January-August, 1984. It’s not clear to
me what Letis’s views were then but obviously he was in agreement with Clark
that the eclectic critical approach was not based on the traditional and
confessional view of Scripture.
Letis supported the Byzantine
ecclesiastical text family of manuscripts but unfortunately did not agree that
the autographs were inerrant and says that infallibility did not include
inerrancy:
Prior to
Warfield’s arrival at Princeton, no Princetonian had attained expert status in
the young discipline of New Testament text criticism. Germany was the domain of
these studies. It is interesting to note that in the absence of this, the
founding professor at Princeton Seminary, Archibald Alexander, felt no compunction
about admitting the autographs were not inerrant, noting that it is even
possible that some of the autographs, if we had them, might not be altogether
free from such errors as arise from the slip of the pen, as the apostles and
and [“had”]. amanuensis[-es] who were not inspired. [11] Alexander could afford
to admit this error, because for him, as it was for the scholastics to whom he
was indebted, the primary locus of authority was the in-hand texts at his
disposal. For him there was no radical discontinuity between the lost
autographs and the text he had before him. Therefore, if the extant text
manifested errors the likelihood was strong that they were there originally.
Letis, Theodore.
The Ecclesiastical Text: Criticism,
Biblical Authority & the Popular Mind (Kindle Locations 327-336). Just
and Sinner Publications. Kindle Edition.
Although I agree with Letis’s
critique of Warfield, I completely disagree that the autographs could have
contained any errors whatsoever. As Dr.
Clark once said, God does not breathe out errors, mistakes, contradictions,
myths, fables, or irrational statements.
The lower text critics start with the axiom that Scripture contains
errors and irrational statements that the orthodox scribes tried to fix by
harmonization and editing the autographs to make the readings more logical,
orthodox, and smooth. But is it so? As Dr. Clark pointed out, it is just as
likely that the scribes who disagreed with the orthodox position edited out
orthodox statements that they viewed as either wrong or corrupt readings. It could just as well be that the later
majority text family preserves the original readings from the autographs and
the earlier copies were lost. The
earliest dated manuscripts could just be corrupted and redacted manuscripts
done by heretics.
The point I wish to make from the
above discussion is that unless the Holy Scriptures are the plenary and
verbally inspired or God-breathed words of God (Matthew 4:4) we have no basis
for Christian theology as derived from the special revelation of God. Language is propositional knowledge and God
determined to give us knowledge of Himself in written language, not through
empirical sensations.
Alvin Plantinga’s Foundationalism
Although I am no professional
scholar, I have read widely. One of the
Christian philosophers I read in seminary was Alvin Plantinga. I use the term Christian loosely here because
although Plantinga came from a Christian Reformed Church background his
theology is not actually Reformed any longer.
Plantinga taught at Notre Dame in the philosophy department for many
years and after his retirement he returned to Calvin College to teach as a
professor emeritus. [See: Biography: Closer to Truth]. Admittedly, being a full time worker, I have
not had the opportunity to read the extensive works of Plantinga so I will
limit myself to what I have learned about his view that belief in God is
foundational to human knowledge or properly basic to human knowledge. This sounds a lot like he is saying that
knowledge of God is innate in man as the image of God. Of course, Plantinga does not consider
himself to be an Evangelical Christian so he is free to moderate somewhere
inbetween fundamentalism and liberalism—if there is any such thing as halfway
between truth and error I suppose you could call it middle ground. This also brings to mind the logical argument
for an excluded middle. However, knowing
Plantinga’s exposure to the doctrine of common grace and the emphasis on the
sciences as natural revelation, it should be no surprise that he takes a
rationalistic view of epistemology. Although
Plantinga rejects the need for proving God’s existence, he also denies that
special revelation in the Bible is the axiom or properly basic place to start
in doing apologetics. However, Plantinga’s
view of properly basic beliefs does sound a lot like he holds to an axiomatic
view of belief in God as the starting point for Christianity:
But
foundationalists hold that some beliefs are not based upon other beliefs. (If
you think about it for a second, you can see that this has to be true if we are
going to avoid an infinite regress or circular belief sets.) Some beliefs are
not based upon other beliefs. They are foundational beliefs, or, as Plantinga
calls them, basic beliefs. They are not based on other beliefs. Micah Cobb, Alvin
Plantinga’s “The Reformed Objection to Natural Theology” (Summary).
Although this is not a primary
source, I believe Cobb’s description of Plantinga’s position is accurate. In contrast, Dr. Gordon H. Clark uses the
Westminster Confession of Faith as the basis for his view that the beginning
axiom of Christianity is Holy Scripture, not God. Moreover God is a secondary axiom of the
Christian faith, not the primary axiom and this is precisely because we could
know nothing savingly about God without special revelation in the verbal and
plenary inspired words in the Bible in grammatical and propositional form. Clark would agree that the knowledge of God
is innate in man because man is God’s image. (Genesis 1:27; John 1:9). Clark deduces this
from the Bible, however, since all knowledge of God begins with Scripture. (Matthew 4:4; John 17:17; 2 Timothy 3:16; 2
Peter 1:19-21). According to Clark, man
is the image of God:
The image of God
in man is asserted but not precisely explained in Gen. 1:26-27; 5:1; 9:6; I
Cor. 11:7, and James 3:9. Something of an explanation comes in Col. 3:10 and
Eph. 4:24, where one may infer that the image consists of knowledge or
rationality and righteousness or holiness, from which proceeds dominion over
the creatures. Romans 8:29 confirms this by describing salvation as a process
of conforming the predestined saint to the image of Christ. Dr. Gordon H. Clark, “Image
of God“.
The problem with Plantinga’s view
is that he never shows why the Christian belief in God is different from other
religions which also have a belief in God or gods. He also seems to commit the fallacy of
induction since absolute truth could never be based on casuistic examples. Gordon H. Clark, on the other hand, holds the
view that knowledge is deductive, not inductive. Although Clark was accused of neo-Platonic
dualism or even gnostic tendencies, the fact is that Clark held to a
philosophical view known as Augustinian realism. That is, in contrast to Plato’s world of
ideas, Clark agreed with Augustine’s view that all knowledge is based on
logical propositions that are abstractions thought in the mind. Knowledge must be real because God Himself
thinks and is a non-material spiritual being who exists apart from His creation
and prior to creation. (John 4:24). Man is able to think and do intellectual
abstract thinking in logical form because man is the image of God. Another problem with Plantinga is that he
seems to think that contradictory religions all lead to God, which is the
natural result of taking the common grace view and is a clear implication of
saying that belief in God is properly basic.
If all men have a divine favor with God—albeit a non-saving one—that view
ultimately leads to religious pluralism and religious relativism. Although Plantinga says he is a religious
exclusivist, he feels no need to critique the other world religions. In practice, therefore, Plantinga is not all
that exclusivist since he seems to have no problem with not evangelizing the
lost and warning them about the judgment to come. If belief in God is properly basic, which God
is properly basic? The Muslim
Allah? One of the Hindu gods? How about the Mormon tri-theistic gods? (Cf. Deuteronomy 6:4; 2 Corinthians 11:3-4;
13:14). [See: Pluralism: A Defense of Religious Exclusivism]. Ironically, those who accuse classical
Calvinists of hyper-Calvinism are in fact the very ones who do not reach out to
evangelize, persuade, and confront those who have no saving knowledge of the
Gospel.
In the next post I will show that
the oxymoron of “reformed” libertarianism is really based on common grace, not
a biblical epistemology. But due to the
time restraints I will return to the
issue of foundationalism and reformed libertarianism in the next post. Please be patient since it takes considerable
time and thought to post coherent essays.
No comments:
Post a Comment